Measuring aggression in the lab is hard
Psychologists often study
aggression in lab-based settings. However,
some people are unconvinced that commonly-used lab-based aggression paradigms actually
demonstrate aggression, which, they claim, limits the evidentiary value of
results from studies that use those paradigms.
Rather than dig in heels, I have tried to think of ways that researchers
can frame their criticisms to make these discussions more productive.
I believe that most criticisms of
lab-based aggression paradigms take on one of two flavors: The behavior was not
believed to have been harmful or the behavior was not believed to have been caused
by a cognitive process involving aggressive cognitions.
The definition of aggression identifies the sources of criticisms
Aggression is a behavior that is
done with the intent to harm another individual who is believed to want to
avoid receiving the behavior. Thus, to
demonstrate aggression in the lab requires two factors: (a) a harmful behavior and
(b) that behavior must be believed to have been caused by a cognitive process
that involved an intent to harm and a belief the recipient wanted to avoid experiencing
the behavior (i.e., collectively referred to as “aggressive cognitions” herein). If both factors are present, aggression has
occurred; if both factors are not present, aggression has not occurred. Conceptually simple, yet hard to execute.
Demonstrating harmful behaviors in the lab
Neither the IRB nor most
researchers will allow participants to actually
harm another person just for the sake of testing a hypothesis. So, you cannot even demonstrate an
unambiguously “harmful” behavior in the lab.
This is a big deal. It is like
researchers who are interested in the phenomenon of “eating ice cream” and the
IRB won’t allow participants in your lab to actually eat ice cream. For this reason, aggression researchers must
use “ethically palatable” behaviors that minimally meet the criterion of being
harmful, but really don’t involve people harming one another.
Some examples of previously-used
lab-based behaviors include sending irritating sound blasts to another person
(who typically do not exist), selecting how much hot sauce will ostensibly be
served to a person who dislikes spicy foods, sticking pins into a Voodoo Doll
of another person to “inflict harm,” choosing how long another person will hold
an uncomfortable Yoga pose, etc. It is
not that aggression researchers think these are super harmful behaviors; but
these are reasonable tasks that can be considered a little harmful, are
quantifiable, can be done in a lab environment, don’t put anybody in harm’s way,
etc. In other words, these tasks are
pragmatic, not ideal.
Some people legitimately doubt
whether these behaviors meet the “harmfulness” criterion (e.g., is a sound
blast really “harmful”?). And, I would
suspect that most aggression researchers would readily concede that these
behaviors are artificial, contrived, and open to debate on whether they are “harmful”. If the opinion is that these behaviors are not
“harmful,” then, by definition, these behaviors cannot be considered aggressive.
I sincerely hear and understand these
criticisms. Nevertheless, researchers obviously
cannot allow participants to actually harm another person within a lab
environment.
Inferring the presence of aggressive cognitions in the lab
It is insufficient merely to
demonstrate that a harmful behavior has occurred; the cognitive process that
causes those behaviors must involve, in some (usually undefined) capacity,
aggressive cognitions. If aggressive
cognitions were not involved, then the resulting behavior is not aggression, regardless
of how harmful the behavior was.
Aggression researchers attempt to create
a context from which aggressive cognitions can be inferred. For example, researchers may tell
participants that a specific behavior (e.g., pressing a button) will cause a
specific event (e.g., send an unpleasant noise) that has a specific effect
(e.g., another person will experience the unpleasant noise). Thus, observing the behavior allows the
researcher to infer the behavior was done with a known intent and with a known
consequence. If the behavior was harmful
and aggressive cognitions were assumed to be involved in the cognitive process
that caused those behaviors, then the resulting behavior can be assumed to be
aggressive.
Some critics point out that several
cognitive processes also can produce the same behavior; thus, there is no
reason to favor a cognitive process involving aggressive cognitions over these
other cognitive processes. For example, participants may perceive a particular
task as competitive (rather than as an opportunity to aggress), participants
may engage in “mischievous responding,” or participants may intuit the study’s
hypotheses and behave according to what they believe the hypotheses are.
The argument goes like this. A cognitive process with “aggressive
cognitions” may cause a harmful behavior (if a, then b), but observing a
harmful behavior does not necessarily imply the behavior was caused by a cognitive
process involving “aggressive cognitions” (b, therefore a) because there are
several cognitive processes (e.g., competition, mischievous responding,
socially-desirable responding, etc.) that also can cause the same harmful
behaviors (if x, then b or if y, then b).
Believing that the presence of a harmful behavior necessarily implies the presence of a cognitive process involving
aggressive cognitions is a logical error known as affirming the
consequent.
Perhaps an unappreciated idea is
that these criticisms cut both ways.
Just because it is possible that a “non-aggressive” cognitive process
can cause a harmful behavior does not mean that it did. For example, just because it is possible that
some participants in some instances may think sending sound blasts to another
person is competitive (and not aggressive) does not mean that any specific
instance of this behavior does not meet
the criteria for aggression. It is
possible those sound blasts in this instance were being sent with the intent to
aggress against the recipient and, thus, the behavior would meet the criteria for aggression. Further, if the same
context (e.g., experiencing an insult) both causes a harmful behavior in the
lab (e.g., sound blasts) and harmful behavior out of the lab (e.g., punching
another person), this may cause one to slightly favor the cognitive process
involving aggressive cognitions when observing the behavior in the lab. Ultimately, researchers need to use their
judgment on whether it is plausible to infer that a cognitive process involved
aggressive cognitions. And reasonable
people will disagree on what is plausible.
Another common approach to
inferring the presence of aggressive cognitions is to ask participants why they
exhibited a behavior. For example, you could
ask participants to report whether they sent loud sound blasts to be
“aggressive” or not. If they say “yes,”
then the resulting harmful behavior may be considered aggressive.
As straightforward as this approach
appears, it has its own limitations.
First, this approach assumes that participants have introspective access
to their cognitive processes (which is not a requirement for the resulting
behavior to be considered aggressive).
Second, the abovementioned criticisms of the processes causing harmful
behaviors also apply to the processes causing participants’ self-reported
motives. For example, participants may
report having done a behavior to be aggressive merely because they are being “mischievous,”
or participants may intuit the study hypotheses and “play along” with what they
believe the hypotheses are. Simply put, there are many cognitive processes
that can become expressed in a response of “I did that behavior to be
aggressive”.
As with the criticisms of the
behaviors typically observed in lab-based aggression paradigms, I sincerely
hear and understand the critiques about whether aggressive cognitions are
involved in the process causing those behaviors. There is no avoiding the fact that inferring
characteristics of cognitive processes is hard to do and that different
researchers have different ideas of what would convince them to infer the
presence of aggressive cognitions.
Framing and addressing the critiques
It is hard to demonstrate
aggression in a laboratory setting in a way that will result in wide-spread
agreement. But hard does not mean
impossible. And disagreements need not
be permanent. Here are things that I believe will facilitate
discussions about the value of these paradigms.
1.
For those offering critiques, be specific about the
target of criticism. Do you not believe
the behavior was harmful? Or do you
believe there was an alternative cognitive explanation for the observed harmful
behavior? Or both? Clarity in the critique offers clarity in the
ways in which researchers can improve their methods. Those
who are unconvinced by current methods should state what methods or evidence
would be convincing. Inconvincibility is a conversation stopper.
2.
For researchers, to demonstrate aggression you need to
both (a) demonstrate a harmful behavior and (b) this behavior must be assumed
to have been caused by a cognitive process with “aggressive” cognitions. Thus, you need to both argue why you believe
the observed behavior is harmful and you need to argue why you believe the
cognitive process involved aggressive cognitions. Without both of these things, you cannot
claim you have measured aggression. Keep
in mind that people might will argue the behavior was not harmful,
people might will argue there was an alternative cognitive process that
caused the behavior, or both. Such
critiques are OK, it’s called science. Take
these criticisms seriously and use them as motivation to improve your methods.
Comments
Post a Comment